Vol. 43 No. 2 (2023)
Articles

Public Reasons and Moral Normativity

Yohan Molina
Pontificia Universidad Católica de Chile, Santiago, Chile

Published 2023-11-01

Keywords

  • Reasons,
  • Publicity,
  • Korsgaard,
  • Kant,
  • Value
  • Razones,
  • Publicidad,
  • Korsgaard,
  • Kant,
  • Valor

Abstract

This paper aims to discuss the public conception of reasons proposed by Christine Korsgaard to justify moral obligation in her books The Sources of Normativity (1996a) and Self-constitution (2009). It will be mainly emphasized two connected points. On the one hand, Korsgaard’s description of the public nature of reasons, which states that their normative force is potentially shared, is not enough for her own account of universal moral obligations, because these obligations are based on the existing shared normativity of reasons. On the other hand, Korsgaard does not consider her own explanation of the normativity of reasons to explain the movement from the shareable normative force of reasons to their existing shared normativity, and this explanation has damaging consequences to support the unconditional respect for humanity. Furthermore, I will review alternative ways in which the publicity of reasons can be understood and outline a trilemma for Korsgaard’s justification of morality.

References

  1. Beyleveld, D. (2015). Korsgaard v. Gewirth on universalization: Why Gewirthians are Kantians and Kantians ought to be Gewirthians. Journal of Moral Philosophy, 12(5), 573-597.
  2. Cholbi, M. J. (1999). Egoism and the publicity of reason: A reply to Korsgaard. Social Theory and Practice, 25(3), 491-517. http://www.jstor.org/stable/23560385
  3. De Maagt, S. (2018). Korsgaard’s other argument for interpersonal morality: The argument from the sufficiency of agency. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 21, 887-902.
  4. Frankfurt, H. G. (1971). Freedom of the will and the concept of a person. The Journal of Philosophy, 68, 5-20.
  5. Garnett, M. (2011). Practical reason and the unity of agency. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 41(3), 449-467.
  6. Gert, J. (2002). Korsgaard’s private-reasons argument. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 64(2), 303-324.
  7. Kant, I. (1998). Groundwork of the metaphysics of morals (Cambridge Texts in the History of Philosophy). Cambridge University Press.
  8. Kerstein, S. J. (2001). Korsgaard’s Kantian arguments for the value of humanity. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 31(1), 23-52.
  9. Korsgaard, C. M. (1996a). The sources of normativity. Cambridge University Press.
  10. Korsgaard, C. M. (1996b). Kant’s formula of humanity. En Creating the kingdom of ends (pp.106-132). Cambridge University Press.
  11. Korsgaard, C. M. (1996c). The reasons we can share: An attack on the distinction between agent-relative and agent-neutral values. En Creating the kingdom of ends (pp. 275-310). Cambridge University Press.
  12. Korsgaard, C. M. (2009). Self-constitution: Agency, identity, and integrity. Oxford University Press.
  13. Korsgaard, C. M. (2021). Valuing our humanity. En O. Sensen & R. Dean (Eds.). Respect: Philosophical essays (pp. 171-191). Oxford University Press.
  14. LeBar, M. (2001). Korsgaard, Wittgenstein, and the Mafioso. Southern Journal of Philosophy, 39(2), 261-271.
  15. Nagel, Th. (1970). The view from nowhere. Oxford University Press.
  16. Norman, R. J. (2000). Public reasons and the ‘private language’ argument. Philosophical Investigations, 23(4), 292-314.
  17. O’ Day, K. (1998). Normativity and interpersonal reasons. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 1(1), 61-83.
  18. Pauer-Studer, H. (2018). Korsgaard’s constitutivism and the possibility of bad action. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 21(1), 37-56.
  19. Sensen, O. (2011). Kant on human dignity. De Gruyter.
  20. Skidmore, J. (2002). Skepticism about practical reason: Transcendental arguments and their limits. Philosophical Studies, 109, 121-141.
  21. Wallace, R. (2009). The publicity of reasons. Philosophical Perspectives, 23(1), 471-497.
  22. Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical Investigation. Blackwell.